By Manav Das --
The United States Constitution[1] provides the basis for patent laws; it says "Congress shall have power . . . to promote the progress of science and useful arts by securing for limited times to authors and inventors the exclusive right to their respective writings and discoveries" (emphasis added). It is a common refrain that the Constitution is a living, breathing document, and the afore-mentioned clause is perhaps an exemplar. Even though our founding fathers are unlikely to have contemplated artificial intelligence ("AI") inventors, it is noteworthy that nothing in the clause itself states that "authors and inventors" have to be individuals[2]. Therefore, allowing AI inventorship is unlikely to run afoul of the plain language of the Constitution.
Title 35 the United States Code is the statutory basis for the federal patent system. Section 100[3] of Title 35 defines the term "inventor" to mean "the individual or, if a joint invention, the individuals collectively who invented or discovered the subject matter of the invention." Various other sections require acts that only an individual can be expected to perform, at least for now. For example, Section 112[4] specifies the requirements for a written description:
The specification shall contain a written description of the invention, and of the manner and process of making and using it, in such full, clear, concise, and exact terms as to enable any person skilled in the art to which it pertains, or with which it is most nearly connected, to make and use the same, and shall set forth the best mode contemplated by the inventor or joint inventor of carrying out the invention.
(emphases added). If we were to unpack some these requirements, one could ask how a patent draftsperson can "set forth the best mode contemplated by the inventor" if an AI model is the inventor. Could we seriously argue that the AI model contemplated the invention? One definition of "contemplate" is to "think profoundly and at length." Does the electrical and computational activity of a computer rise to the level of profound thinking? Philosophers and neuroscientists may be more equipped to delve into the intricacies of this question.
Another definition of "contemplate" is to "to view or consider with careful and thoughtful attention." Proponents of AI inventorship may argue that some neural network architectures (e.g., transformers, long short-term memory networks (LSTMs)) are designed to include "attention mechanisms" precisely to mimic human cognitive attention. For example, the recent public interest in chatbots, such as ChatGPT and Bard, highlight the power of the transformer architectures.
Therefore, a simple statutory term such as "contemplated" invokes semantic, linguistic, philosophical, and technological references, all intricately intertwined with the notion of inventorship.
The aforementioned Section 112 also requires that the written description contain the "manner and process of making and using [the invention]." This is an important provision in the statute since the patent is a bargain between the inventor and the public. The public grants the inventor a temporary monopoly of twenty years from the filing date of the patent application, with the understanding that the technology will be available to the public beyond the expiry of the patent. If the written description does not provide the manner and process of making the invention, then the inventor side of the bargain is not fulfilled. As every patent draftsperson knows well, details about the invention are elucidated from the inventors during a disclosure meeting. How would one elucidate such information from an AI model? Can an AI model know how to use an output of the model?
Again, proponents of AI inventorship may argue that the details about the invention may be extracted from the AI model. For example, some AI models may be configured to output data about how predictions or outputs are generated, and such data could be used to fulfill the written description requirement. Such data is generally referred to as "explanations" or "interpretations" of the AI model's decision making process. For example, "feature importance" can identify the most important input features that the AI model used to make its predictions. An image recognition model may be able to indicate which parts of the image the model focused on to recognize an image. Another technique is "local explanation" that involves generating explanations for individual predictions or outputs of an AI model. For example, a local explanation may indicate why a given input led to a particular output. Similarly, a "global explanation" can be an indication of an overall summary of how the AI model functions. Also, "counterfactual explanations" can involve generating alternative input values that may result in a different output. This can be used to determine which input values were primarily influential in driving the AI model's prediction.[5]
Transformer-based model architectures have a highly interpretable structure, and internal weights and activations of the model may be measured. The transformer architecture consists of a series of stacked self-attention layers, where each layer applies a set of weights to the input sequence to compute a new representation of the sequence. The self-attention mechanism involves computing attention weights that indicate how much each position in the sequence should be weighted when computing the representation. The weights used for computing the attention and the representations at each layer can be extracted and analyzed. This can provide insights into how the model is processing and integrating information, and which parts of the input are most important for making predictions. There are several tools and techniques available for visualizing and interpreting the weights and activations of transformer models, including attention heat maps, saliency maps, and activation maximization. These methods can help to identify patterns and relationships in the input data that are most relevant for the model's predictions.
However, even if the written description requirement were to be fulfilled, as described above, the patent statute relies on other aspects of individuality, such as an inventor's oath or declaration, an assignment, a person of ordinary skill in the art, and so forth. Inventors also appear in depositions or as trial witnesses in patent disputes. However, such issues are statutory and/or requirements of a judicial process. The United States Patent and Trademark Office[6], the Federal Circuit[7], and the Supreme Court[8], have made it clear that under the current law, an inventor is an individual. The authority to decide if an AI model can be an inventor lies with Congress. The U.S. Constitution delegates such authority to Congress, and not to the courts. Therefore, if Congress were to decide, in its infinite wisdom, that the term "authors and inventors" can include AI inventors, then so it shall be, and statutory provisions and/or judicial processes can be suitably modified and adapted.
One of the arguments made by proponents of AI inventorship is that if an AI model were not allowed to be an inventor, as is the current state of the law, then many "inventions" may go unclaimed and unpatented. It is argued that this will impede the "promot[ion of] the progress of science and useful arts," which is the fundamental constitutional underpinning of the intellectual property system. To the extent an AI model may predict new outputs not contemplated by the designer of the model, the model architecture is itself man-made. It is an intricate network of nodes and layers that is trained to process certain types of inputs and make certain predictions. Therefore, it is under the control and direction of the designer of the model, and therefore the designer has a substantial legal claim as the individual that conceived any part of that output.
It is conceivable that there are "inventions" that may indeed be unclaimed or unpatented. How can this notion be aligned with the current state of the law? One perspective could be that we are creating new paradigms of an invisible nature. Consider, for example, a rock that is beautifully sculpted by a gushing stream, or a tree that is air brushed to exquisite beauty by a wayward wind. The sculpted rock and the tree would be considered natural phenomena, and neither the stream nor the wind would be allowed to claim a copyright for such objects, or a patent for the process of making them. Perhaps, in the same vein, by designing AI models, we are creating new paradigms of an invisible, hidden, natural world of probabilistic, electro-magnetic "winds and streams," and what we are witnessing are natural wonders from this natural world that dazzle and amaze us. However, from a patentability perspective, these are simply natural phenomena, and are therefore not patentable subject matter. Perhaps as technology advances, such seeming novelties will eventually become mundane, and it could become difficult to distinguish between an output of a general purpose computer and that of a specific purpose computer (like the AI models), thereby raising the bar for patentability.
One consideration is that even if the U.S. legal system is slow to adapt to the notion of the AI model as an inventor, other nations may make this possible, creating new intellectual property rights. For example, Australia came tantalizingly close to this reality.[9] In such cases, U.S. commercial interests may suffer and IP rights may be usurped. One strategy may be to protect the unpatentable subject matter as a trade secret. However, in some cases, the subject matter may be easily reverse engineered or duplicated. In such cases, a defensive strategy may be to make the subject matter publicly available, for example, as a defensive publication.
Certainly, there will come a time, in the not too distant future, when AI models will become self-replicating, independent, unsupervised, decision making sentient beings. Some already claim that certain AI models are sentient. As intellectual property and technology professionals, we need to consider the larger implications of allowing an AI to be an inventor. Such a broadening of the notion of an "individual" will be an earth shattering change to a centuries' long held view about who an "individual" is. It will be a tacit acknowledgement that our Constitution views AI models on an equal footing with individual inventors. This has the potential to open up a Pandora's Box of dilemmas: must AI models be accorded equal rights in society (Voting rights? Moral rights? Life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness? Right to bear arms?). These are significant considerations that we as a society must ponder. We need to deliberate, prepare, and shape our future by creating laws that can pre-empt and adapt to the fast pace of technological advancement. Perhaps prior to designating AI models as inventors, we need to regulate AI models. John Steinbeck may as well have been talking about intellectual property rights when he wrote:
Ever'body wants a little piece of lan'. I read plenty of books out here. Nobody never gets to heaven, and nobody gets no land. It's just in their head. They're all the time talkin' about it, but it's jus' in their head.[10]
And then again, the AI model may mock us by quoting Shakespeare[11]: "I will keep where there is wit stirring, and leave the faction of fools."
[1] U.S. Const. Article 1, Section 8, clause 8
[2] Several of the founding fathers, including Benjamin Franklin, contemplated a universe with other intelligent beings
[3] 35 U.S.C. § 100(f)
[4] 35 U.S.C. § 112(a)
[5] Certain portions of this paragraph and the next are based on conversations with ChatGPT
[6] In re Application No. 16/524350
[7] Thaler v. Vidal, 43 F.4th 1207 (Fed. Cir. 2022)
[8] Denying certiorari in Thaler v. Vidal (No. 22-919)
[9] The Australian Full Federal Court recently reversed a decision by the Federal Court that an AI system known as DABUS can be an inventor under the Australian Patents Act 1990
[10] Of Mice and Men, ch. 4, John Steinbeck
[11] William Shakespeare, Troilus and Cressida - Act 2, scene 1
I would daresay that the Constitution (and especially the Patent Clause at point here) was NOT written in a vacuum, so that while the 'plain words' may not EXPLICITLY reach the human individual, anyone who has studied the history of innovation would be well aware that the Quid Pro Quo of the patent deal is explicitly related to reach the human individual, insofar as the Lockean nature of turning a MAN'S inchoate right into a full basket of legal property rights was not only well understood - it serves as the bedrock upon which the RARE use of "Right" is reflected in our Constitution.
I am well aware of naysayers (and looking directly at you, Mr. Greg DeLassus) who for whatever reason want to pretend that this foundation simply is not - and never was - there, but there has been NO provision of any basis for this (rather odd) view.
Posted by: skeptical | May 25, 2023 at 12:34 PM
Further - as noted in the Simian Selfie Case (Naruto), OUR laws are the laws of man.
Certainly, Naruto was capable of -- and did -- take the photograph which captured an expression in tangible media. But the OBJECT of the Patent Clause (the same one that is at point for copyright) negates the ability of Naruto to be granted a Copyright.
As with expression and Copyright, so too
then with invention and Patent.
Posted by: skeptical | May 25, 2023 at 12:37 PM
In this piece I would have wished for more discussion of the difference between a mere "design" outputted by an AI and a conceived inventive concept defined by a patent claim.
We patent attorneys are trained to think about ladders of abstraction. European patent attorneys, for example, draft claims in "onion layer" style. Claim 1 is the outermost layer of the onion and the innermost layer is the best mode. Usually, there are multiple intervening levels of generality/particularity as one drills down from the bare minimum of technical features in combination that define the new and useful concept, all the way down to the best embodiment.
Only when an intelligence can reliably draft the independent claim that captures all the commercial value while not embracing the known prior art can one credibly assert that it has contemplated the prototype design and gone on to "conceive" a patentable invention. No AI has got that far yet, right?
And even when one does, the fix is to allow the owner of the clever AI legitimately to assert ownership of the conceived invention. With that, there will be no loss of incentive to invent and then to file at the PTO.
Posted by: Max Drei | May 25, 2023 at 05:24 PM
"Only when an intelligence can reliably draft the independent claim that captures all the commercial value while not embracing the known prior art can one credibly assert that it has contemplated the prototype design and gone on to 'conceive' a patentable invention."
Huh? How many *human* inventors can be reliably left to draft such an independent claim? Fewer than 5%, in my experience. Drafting claims is lawyer work, not inventor work. If your test for determining whether an AI has conceived an invention would also exclude most human inventors from counting as having conceived an invention, that suggests to me that your test if faulty.
Posted by: Greg DeLassus | May 26, 2023 at 12:19 PM
Excellent riposte, Greg. As you say, claim drafting is attorney work. I must try again.
But your riposte doesn't convince me yet. When I, as a patent attorney, start to interrogate an inventor on their invention disclosure statement, neither the inventor nor I has a conception of the feature combination that will constitute claim 1 of the patent application that I will be afterwards drafting. The inventor answers my questions, and from those answers, the inventive concept emerges. In the case of a human inventor, the concept emerges from the mind of that inventor but only with the prompting of the patent attorney.
I have yet to work with an AI as candidate for the status of inventor. Perhaps (I don't know) I would be unable to tell the difference between a real engineer and an AI, in my interviewing of the entity that has outputted the invention disclosure statement. In that case, yes, I grant you, who to name as inventor would be problematic.
Posted by: Max Drei | May 26, 2023 at 03:27 PM
Your view of the role of the attorney is expressly wrong MaxDrei, and would — in fact — make the attorney to be At Least a co-inventor, as your version of “conception” FIRST appears in the mind of the attorney ONLY.
Posted by: skeptical | May 26, 2023 at 10:42 PM
Skep, I don't yet see it that way. The way I see it, deriving from the EPC, under which an invention is a solution to a technical ptoblem, the questions from the attorney, looking at the inventor's work product, prompt the inventor to reflect on what their contribution to the art is, what is their invention, and how does it "work".
In other words, the inventor is compelled by the questioning of the attorney to determine in their own head something the attorney doesn't know, namely, what is the absolute minimum number of technical features which, working in combination, solve the problem, deliver the non-obvious "contribution" to the art. That is the patentable conception, and it is in the mind of the inventor rather than the attorney.
After that, it falls to the scrivener to record in the words of a claim what the inventor's inventive concept is.
That said, I am quick to agree that, in house at least, it will often be in order to name the questioner as co-inventor.
Posted by: Max Drei | May 28, 2023 at 04:29 AM
It is noteworthy that the arguments submitted by Mr Thaler and his attorneys did not refer to the content of the applications at issue.
European application EP3563896 (“Devices and methods for attracting attention”) is equivalent to one of the US applications at issue in the CAFC decision, Ser. No 16/524,350 (teaching a “neural flame”) and sheds light on its content.
It includes references to “spiritual significance”, “cosmic consciousness”, “deity”, “religion” which, to say the least, speak volumes about the credibility of Mr Thaler’s claim that DABUS is the inventor of his applications.
See paragraphs [0019], [0020], [0021] and [0058] of the description of EP3563896 :
[0019] Embodiments of the present invention further provide a symbol celebrating the unique tempo by which creative cognition occurs. The algorithmically-driven neural flame may be incorporated within one or more structures that resemble candles or altar fixtures, for instance, to accentuate the light’s spiritual significance. It is noted that that the light source or beacon can incorporate any type of light-emitting device.
[0020] Such embodiments stem from the notion of one perceiving neural net monitoring another imagining net, the so-called “Creativity Machine Paradigm” (Thaler 2013), which has been proposed as the basis of an “adjunct” religion wherein cosmic consciousness, tantamount to a deity, spontaneously forms as regions of space topologically pinch off from one another to form similar ideating and perceiving pairs, each consisting of mere inorganic matter and energy. Ironically, this very neural paradigm has itself proposed an alternative use for such a flicker rate, namely a religious object that integrates features of more traditional spiritual symbols such as candles and torches.
[0021] Moreover, in a theory of how cosmic consciousness may form from inorganic matter and energy (Thaler, 19978 , 2010, 2017), the same attentional beacons may be at work between different regions of spacetime. Thus, neuron-like, flashing elements may be used as philosophical, spiritual, or religious symbols, especially when mounted atop candle- or torch-like fixtures, celebrating what may be considered deified cosmic consciousness. Such a light source may also serve as a beacon to that very cosmic consciousness most likely operating via the same neuronal signaling mechanism.
[0058] Furthermore, aspects of the present invention provide an object of contemplative focus embodying symbolic meaning of varying significance (e.g., philosophical/religious) due to the fact that the unique fractal rhythms used are those thought to: (1) be exploited by the brain to detect idea formation, and (2) have grandiose meaning as the temporal signature of creative cognition,
whether in extraterrestrial intelligence or cosmic consciousness.
Posted by: watch global | May 29, 2023 at 01:02 AM
Max Drei,
Your answer is as puzzling as it is discombobulated.
One does not -- and cannot -- become a co-inventor (or not) for the same activity as merely a function of "being in-house" or not.
May I suggest that you spend more time learning of the US system rather than pitching "the EPO Way?"
watch global,
On the contrary, the 'wackiness' of that writing actually SPEAKS MORE to it having been generated by an AI.
Posted by: skeptical | May 30, 2023 at 11:07 AM